George Weigel on Pre-emption, Just War and the Defense of World Order

U.S. Scholar Weighs In on the Debate over Iraq

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Share this Entry

WASHINGTON, D.C., SEPT. 22, 2002 (Zenit.org).- Amid the debate over possible military action against Iraq, ZENIT will be publishing interviews that reflect a diversity of views on the situation. These interviews are in addition to the usual reports on pronouncements by John Paul II and bishops.

Here, ZENIT turned to George Weigel, senior fellow of the Ethics and Public Policy Center in Washington, and the author, most recently, of “The Courage to Be Catholic: Crisis, Reform, and the Future of the Church” (Basic Books).

His recent Pope John XXIII Lecture at the Catholic University of America Law School, “The Just War Tradition and the World After Sept. 11,” may be found in the Spring 2002 issue of the Catholic University Law Review.

* * *

ZENIT: Much of the opposition against U.S. military action centers on worries about endorsing the concept of a pre-emptive strike. What does Catholic moral teaching have to say on this matter?

Weigel: As the classic just-war tradition evolved over the centuries, three situations satisfied the criteria of “just cause”: defense against an aggression under way, recovery of something wrongfully taken, and/or punishment for evil.

Modern just-war thinking, which is reflected in articles 2 and 51 of the U.N. Charter, has tended to limit “just cause” to “defense against an aggression under way.” But we should note that the idea of a moral obligation to “humanitarian intervention” in cases of genocide — of which Pope John Paul II spoke at the Rome-based U.N. Food and Agriculture Organization in 1992 — raises interesting questions about reviving the classic category of “punishment for evil.”

In the case of Iraq, the crucial issue in the moral analysis is what we mean by an “aggression under way.” When a vicious regime that has not hesitated to use chemical weapons against its own people and against a neighboring country, a regime that has no concept of the rule of law and that flagrantly violates its international obligations, works feverishly to obtain and deploy further weapons of mass destruction, I think a compelling moral case can be made that this is a matter of an “aggression under way.”

The nature of the regime, which is the crucial factor in the analysis, makes that plain. It surely makes no moral sense to say that the U.S. or the international community can only respond with armed force when an Iraqi missile carrying a weapon of mass destruction has been launched, or is being readied for launch.

To be sure, there are serious questions of prudence to be addressed in thinking through the question of military action against the Iraqi regime. At the level of moral principle, however, it seems to me that there are, in fact, instances where it is not only right to “go first,” but “going first” may even be morally obligatory. And I think this may well be one of those instances.

Q: War is seen as increasingly unacceptable, in an age of weapons of mass destruction. Yet those in favor of action against Iraq argue that forceful action is necessary, precisely to eliminate this type of arms. Can we reconcile these fears of not wanting to spark off destructive conflict, while keeping undesirable regimes from using chemical, biological or nuclear weapons?

Weigel: President Bush’s address at West Point this past June clearly linked the war against terrorism, and the possibility of military action against aggressor states with weapons of mass destruction, to the pursuit of world order: an order based on justice and freedom. This speech has not been taken seriously enough by the president’s critics, in my view.

There is a great deal of concern, in Europe and elsewhere, about the precedent that would be set by overriding the “presumption of sovereign immunity” that all nation-states enjoy. I would respond that this presumption assumes that the state in question displays at least a minimum of agreement to minimal international norms of order.

A regime like Saddam Hussein’s in Iraq cannot be granted that assumption — because its behavior has demonstrated that it holds the principles of international order in contempt. Some states, because of the regime’s clearly aggressive intent and because there are no effective internal controls on the regime’s behavior, simply cannot be permitted to acquire weapons of mass destruction.

Just-war thinking begins with a basic moral judgment: that legitimate public authorities have a moral obligation to defend and pursue the peace of order, which is composed of justice and freedom. History has shown that that kind of peace can be advanced, in certain precise circumstances, by the proportionate, discriminate and strategically wise use of armed force.

Q: Many are calling for no action to be taken without U.N. approval. Up to what point is a nation obliged to submit to international authorities before commencing war?

Weigel: The question of “legitimate authority” — a classic just-war category — is a very urgent one today. The U.N. charter itself recognizes a right to national self-defense, which implies that defense against aggression does not require the authorization of the Security Council; it is, rather, an inalienable right of nations.

If the use of military force in a given case is intended, among other things, to advance the cause of world order, it certainly helps at the prudential political level if the use of force is approved by the Security Council. But I don’t think a correct reading of the just-war tradition leads to the conclusion that such prior approval is morally imperative.

It has been said recently that a failure to obtain prior Security Council approval for a U.S. or coalition assault to disarm Iraq of weapons of mass destruction would mean that the “law of the strongest” was replacing international law. I respectfully disagree.

What it would mean is that the United States and allied countries, having made clear that they intend their action to advance the cause of world order to which the U.N. is dedicated, have decided that they have a moral obligation to take measures that the U.N., in its present form and cast of mind, finds it impossible to take — even though those measures are aimed at advancing the Charter’s goals. And that, it seems to me, advances the cause of world order over the long haul.

Q: Can we still speak of a “just war,” or do we need to reformulate traditional principles? What would be some guidelines in any rethinking on this subject?

Weigel: The just-war tradition will always remain normative for the Church because it is rooted in the principles of natural law. What is needed today is a development of the tradition.

I’ve already mentioned the need to refine what we mean by “defense against aggression” — in a world of international terrorist organizations and rogue states — and “legitimate authority” — in a world in which nascent but often ineffective instruments of world order exist.

The just-war criterion of “last resort” also needs refinement: What, for example, does it mean to say that all non-military actions have been tried and failed when we are confronted with a new and lethal type of international actor, a terrorist organization that recognizes no form of power other than violence and that is largely immune to the diplomatic and economic pressures that can be put on states?

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Share this Entry

ZENIT Staff

Support ZENIT

If you liked this article, support ZENIT now with a donation